Results for 'Edythe E. Moulton-Tetlock'

959 found
Order:
  1.  19
    Soothing the Self-Threat of Idea Theft.Sara L. Wheeler-Smith & Edythe E. Moulton-Tetlock - 2024 - Humanistic Management Journal 9 (1):15-51.
    The creative process has the potential to increase wellbeing and foster human flourishing (Dolan and Metcalfe, 2012 ; Forgeard and Eichner, 2014 ; O’Brien and Murray, 2015 ; Conner et al., 2018 ; Kaufman, 2018 ), yet has received little attention in the humanistic management literature. In this paper, we present three experiments showing that idea originators experience greater relationship conflict with counterparts who have committed perceived “idea theft”, i.e., proposed identical or related ideas. We test a model that identifies (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  49
    The 2006 Massachusetts Health Care Reform Act.John E. McDonough & Anthony D. Moulton - 2007 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (S4):115-116.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  25
    Impression management versus intrapsychic explanations in social psychology: A useful dichotomy?Philip E. Tetlock & Antony S. Manstead - 1985 - Psychological Review 92 (1):59-77.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  4.  48
    Social functionalist frameworks for judgment and choice: Intuitive politicians, theologians, and prosecutors.Philip E. Tetlock - 2002 - Psychological Review 109 (3):451-471.
  5.  21
    The Implicit Prejudice Exchange: Islands of Consensus in a Sea of Controversy.Philip E. Tetlock & Hal R. Arkes - 2004 - Psychological Inquiry 15 (4).
  6.  58
    Should “Systems Thinkers” Accept the Limits on Political Forecasting or Push the Limits?Philip E. Tetlock, Michael C. Horowitz & Richard Herrmann - 2012 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 24 (3):375-391.
    Historical analysis and policy making often require counterfactual thought experiments that isolate hypothesized causes from a vast array of historical possibilities. However, a core precept of Jervis's “systems thinking” is that causes are so interconnected that the historian can only with great difficulty imagine causation by subtracting all variables but one. Prediction, according to Jervis, is even more problematic: The more sensitive an event is to initial conditions (e.g., butterfly effects), the harder it is to derive accurate forecasts. Nevertheless, if (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  18
    Tracking Forecasting Accuracy of Geopolitical Schools of Thought—and Causes of Their Predictive Successes and Failures.Philip E. Tetlock - 2024 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 36 (4):515-525.
    International relations theories have often been faulted for not advancing falsifiable forecasts. Given the complexities of geopolitics and the near impossibility of satisfying the “ceteris paribus” clause in scientific hypothesis testing, this criticism imposes an unfair standard. It is reasonable however to ask about the predictive track records of international relations theorists who enter high-stakes policy debates. Whether a neorealist of neo-institutionalist proves an adroit or maladroit forecaster sheds little light on the truth status of their preferred theory but considerable (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  29
    The selfishness-altruism debate: In defense of agnosticism.Philip E. Tetlock - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (4):723-724.
  9. Theory- versus imagination-driven thinking about historical counterfactuals: are we prisoners of our preconceptions?Philip E. Tetlock & Erika Henik - 2005 - In David R. Mandel, Denis J. Hilton & Patrizia Catellani, The psychology of counterfactual thinking. New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  77
    Second thoughts about Expert Political Judgment: reply to the symposium.Philip E. Tetlock - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):467-488.
  11.  72
    Gauging the heuristic value of heuristics.Philip E. Tetlock - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (4):562-563.
    Heuristics are necessary but far from sufficient explanations for moral judgment. This commentary stresses: (a) the need to complement cold, cognitive-economizing functionalist accounts with hot, value-expressive, social-identity-affirming accounts; and (b) the importance of conducting reflective-equilibrium thought and laboratory experiments that explore the permeability of the boundaries people place on the “thinkable.”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. Some thoughts about thought systems.Philip E. Tetlock - 1991 - In Robert S. Wyer & Thomas K. Srull, The Content, Structure, and Operation of Thought Systems. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 4--197.
  13.  57
    The consequences of taking consequentialism seriously.Philip E. Tetlock - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):31-32.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Attributions of Implicit Prejudice, or "Would Jesse Jackson 'Fail' the Implicit Association Test?".Hal R. Arkes & Philip E. Tetlock - 2004 - Psychological Inquiry 15 (4):257-78.
  15.  87
    Cognitive appraisals and emotional experience: Further evidence.A. S. R. Manstead, Philip E. Tetlock & Tony Manstead - 1989 - Cognition and Emotion 3 (3):225-239.
  16.  27
    The Congress Party in Rajasthan: Political Integration and Institution Building in an Indian State.E. C. Moulton & Richard Sisson - 1973 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 93 (4):620.
  17.  37
    The ever‐shifting psychological foundations of democratic theory: Do citizens have the right stuff? [REVIEW]Philip E. Tetlock - 1998 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 12 (4):545-561.
    Timur Kuran's Private Truths, Public Lies makes a compelling case that people often misrepresent their private preferences in response to real or imagined social pressures, that the relative power of competing interest groups to punish opinion deviance and reward conformity determines the patterns and pervasiveness of preference falsification, and that preference falsifi‐cation helps explain such diverse outcomes as the persistence and sudden collapse of communism and the precarious persistence of racial preferences in the United States and of the caste system (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  48
    Debunking the Myth of Value-Neutral Virginity: Toward Truth in Scientific Advertising.David R. Mandel & Philip E. Tetlock - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  31
    Correcting Judgment Correctives in National Security Intelligence.David R. Mandel & Philip E. Tetlock - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9:428814.
    Intelligence analysts, like other professionals, form norms that define standards of tradecraft excellence. These norms, however, have evolved in an idiosyncratic manner that reflects the influence of prominent insiders who had keen psychological insights but little appreciation for how to translate those insights into testable hypotheses. The net result is that the prevailing tradecraft norms of best practice are only loosely grounded in the science of judgment and decision-making. The “common sense” of prestigious opinion leaders inside the intelligence community has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  10
    The internal validity obsession.Gregory Mitchell & Philip E. Tetlock - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    Until social psychology devotes as much attention to construct and external validity as it does to internal validity, the field will continue to produce theories that fail to replicate in the field and cannot be used to meliorate social problems.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Political diversity will improve social psychological science.José L. Duarte, Jarret T. Crawford, Charlotta Stern, Jonathan Haidt, Lee Jussim & Philip E. Tetlock - 2015 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 38:1-54.
    Psychologists have demonstrated the value of diversity – particularly diversity of viewpoints – for enhancing creativity, discovery, and problem solving. But one key type of viewpoint diversity is lacking in academic psychology in general and social psychology in particular: political diversity. This article reviews the available evidence and finds support for four claims: (1) Academic psychology once had considerable political diversity, but has lost nearly all of it in the last 50 years. (2) This lack of political diversity can undermine (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  22.  36
    The Greek Diminutive Suffix -ισκο- -ισκη-. [REVIEW]G. E. K. Moulton - 1915 - The Classical Review 29 (1):23-24.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  34
    Effects of questioning unaware problem solvers in a "verbal conditioning" task.Theodore R. Dixon & Alan E. Moulton - 1970 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 83 (3p1):431.
  24.  31
    Retention of intentional and of incidental learning following response-correlated reinforcement.Theodore R. Dixon & Alan E. Moulton - 1967 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 73 (4p1):600.
  25.  62
    It may be harder than we thought, but political diversity will improve social psychological science.Jarret T. Crawford, José L. Duarte, Jonathan Haidt, Lee Jussim, Charlotta Stern & Philip E. Tetlock - 2015 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 38.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  71
    Grenfell and Hunt's Tebtunis Papyri(Part II.). - The Tebtunis Papyri, Part II. Edited by B. P. Grenfell and A. S. Hunt, with the assistance of E. J. Godspeed. (University of California Publications.) London: Henry Frowde, 1907. Pp. xv + 485. Two Facsimiles and Map. £2 5s. net. [REVIEW]James Hope Moulton - 1908 - Classical Quarterly 2 (02):137-.
    The Tebtunis Papyri, Part II. Edited by B. P. Grenfell and A. S. Hunt, with the assistance of E. J. Godspeed. London: Henry Frowde, 1907. Pp. xv + 485. Two Facsimiles and Map. £2 5s. net.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  13
    Assume a can opener.Cory J. Clark, Calvin Isch, Paul Connor & Philip E. Tetlock - 2024 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 47:e36.
    We propose a friendly amendment to integrative experiment design (IED), adversarial-collaboration IED, that incentivizes research teams from competing theoretical perspectives to identify zones of the design space where they possess an explanatory edge. This amendment is especially critical in debates that have high policy stakes and carry a strong normative-political charge that might otherwise prevent free exchange of ideas.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  26
    Stimulus control of approach behavior.John W. Donahoe, Vincent G. Schulte & Alan E. Moulton - 1968 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 78 (1):21.
  29.  42
    Tetlock and counterfactuals: Saving methodological ambition from empirical findings.Ian S. Lustick - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):427-447.
    In five works spanning a decade, Philip E. Tetlock's interest in counterfactuals has changed. He began with an optimistic desire to make social science more rigorous by identifying best practices in the absence of non-imagined controls for experimentation. Soon, however, he adopted a more pessimistic analysis of the cognitive and psychological barriers facing experts. This shift was brought on by an awareness that experts are not rational Bayesians who continually update their theories to keep up with new information; but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  38
    The Financial Organization of Society. Harold G. Moulton.Walter E. Lagerquist - 1921 - International Journal of Ethics 31 (4):447-448.
  31.  82
    Readings in Industrial Society. L. C. MarshallReadings in the Economics of War. J. M. Clark, W. H. Hamilton, H. G. Moulton[REVIEW]C. E. Ayres - 1919 - International Journal of Ethics 29 (2):242-243.
  32.  32
    Mutilation Mania—The Witch Craze Revisited: An Essay Review of An Alien Harvest.Robert E. Bartholomew - 1992 - Anthropology of Consciousness 3 (1-2):23-25.
    Linda Moulton Howe. An Alien Harvest. Littleton, Colorado: LMH Productions. 1989. Pp. xviii. 455. $55.00. Cloth. ISBN 0‐9620570‐1‐0. Available from Linda Howe Productions, 904 Summit North Drive, Atlanta, Georgia 30324.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  74
    Small Group Predictions on an Uncertain Outcome: The Effect of Nondiagnostic Information.George R. Young II, Kenneth H. Price & Cynthia Claybrook - 2001 - Theory and Decision 50 (2):149-167.
    Research has established that exposure to a combination of diagnostic (i.e., relevant) and nondiagnostic (i.e., irrelevant) information results in predictions that are more regressive than predictions based on diagnostic information (Hackenbrack, 1992; Hoffman and Patton, 1997). This phenomenon has been labeled the dilution effect (e.g., Tetlock and Boettger, 1989) and has been documented when individuals make predictions. This study tests for the dilution effect when small groups make predictions, and examines the effect of using a procedure designed to reduce (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  12
    Small Group Predictions on an Uncertain Outcome: The Effect of Nondiagnostic Information.George Young, Kenneth Price & Cynthia Claybrook - 2001 - Theory and Decision 50 (2):149-167.
    Research has established that exposure to a combination of diagnostic (i.e., relevant) and nondiagnostic (i.e., irrelevant) information results in predictions that are more regressive than predictions based on diagnostic information (Hackenbrack, 1992; Hoffman and Patton, 1997). This phenomenon has been labeled the dilution effect (e.g., Tetlock and Boettger, 1989) and has been documented when individuals make predictions. This study tests for the dilution effect when small groups make predictions, and examines the effect of using a procedure designed to reduce (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  70
    When and Why Do Hedgehogs and Foxes Differ?Frank C. Keil - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):415-426.
    Philip E. Tetlock's finding that "hedgehog" experts (those with one big theory) are worse predictors than "foxes" (those with multiple, less comprehensive theories) offers fertile ground for future research. Are experts as likely to exhibit hedgehog- or fox-like tendencies in areas that call for explanatory, diagnostic, and skill-based expertise-as they did when Tetlock called on experts to make predictions? Do particular domains of expertise curtail or encourage different styles of expertise? Can we trace these different styles to childhood? (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  37
    Judging Judgment.Bruce Bueno de Mesquita - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):355-388.
    Philip E. Tetlock and I agree that forecasting tools are best evaluated in peer-reviewed settings and in comparison not only to expert judgments, but also to alternative modeling strategies. Applying his suggested standards of assessment, however, certain forecasting models not only outperform expert judgments, but also have gone head-to-head with alternative models and outperformed them. This track record demonstrates the capability to make significant, reliable predictions of difficult, complex events. The record has unfolded, contrary to Tetlock's contention, not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  57
    The Abiding Art of Agnes Repplier.Edythe Helen Browne - 1930 - Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 5 (3):396-410.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  60
    The trouble with experts.Paul J. Quirk - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):449-465.
    In his justly celebrated Expert Political Judgment, Philip E. Tetlock evaluates the judgment of economic and political experts by rigorously testing their ability to make accurate predictions. He finds that ability profoundly limited, implying that expert judgment is virtually useless, if not worse. He concludes by proposing a project that would seek to improve experts' performance by holding them publicly accountable for their claims. But Tetlock's methods severely underestimate the value of expert opinion. Despite their notorious disagreements, experts (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  41
    Putting political experts to the test.Zeljka Buturovic - 2010 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 22 (4):389-396.
    In his remarkably meticulous and even-handed 2005 book, Expert Political Judgment, Philip E. Tetlock establishes that the only thing we can count on in the political experts' predictions is that they will underperform-in some cases significantly-the predictions made by mechanical statistical procedures, including random chance. Experts have many uses and Tetlock does not claim that they have no value. However, Tetlock zeroes in on experts' important political role-as prognosticators. Tetlock does not attempt the impossible by trying (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  72
    Value Pluralism, Intuitions, and Reflective Equilibrium.Lisa Tessman - 2013 - Philosophical Topics 41 (2):175-201.
    A constructivist approach to ethics must include some process—such as Rawls’ (1971) reflective equilibrium—for moving from initial evaluative judgments to those that one can affirm. Walker’s (1998; 2003) feminist version of reflective equilibrium incorporates what she calls “transparency testing” to weed out pernicious, ideologically shaped intuitions. However, in light of empirical work on the plurality of values and on the cognitive processes through which people arrive at moral judgments (i.e. an automatic, intuitive process and/or a controlled reasoning process), I raise (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  37
    James Hope Moulton 1863-1917: Parts 1-3.W. Fiddian Moulton, A. S. Peake & Rendel Harris - 1917 - Bulletin of the John Rylands Library 4 (1):10-25.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  40
    The Hermeneutical Turn in American Critical Theory, 1830-1860.Donald Walhout - 1996 - Journal of the History of Ideas 57 (4):683-703.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Hermeneutical Turn in American Critical Theory, 1830–1860M. D. WalhoutLong considered an obscure province of biblical studies, hermeneutics is now familiar territory to American literary critics, along with phenomenology, structuralism, post-structuralism, and the other European theories that have redrawn the map of American criticism in the past twenty-five years. The gradual transformation of hermeneutics into a theory of criticism, and ultimately into a comprehensive theory of the human sciences, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  80
    What is Public Health Legal Preparedness?Anthony D. Moulton, Richard N. Gottfried, Richard A. Goodman, Anne M. Murphy & Raymond D. Rawson - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (4):672-683.
    “Public health legal preparedness” is a term born in the ferment, beginning in the late 1990s, that has led to unprecedented recognition of the essential role law plays in public health and, even more recently, in protecting the public from terrorism and other potentially catastrophic health threats.The initial articulation of public health has not kept pace with rapid evolution in the concept and in practical development of public health preparedness itself. This poses the risk that legal preparedness may fall behind (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  44.  78
    Aligning Ethics with Medical Decision-Making: The Quest for Informed Patient Choice.Benjamin Moulton & Jaime S. King - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (1):85-97.
    Medical practice should evolve alongside medical ethics. As our understanding of the ethical implications of physician-patient interactions becomes more nuanced, physicians should integrate those lessons into practice. As early as the 1930s, epidemiological studies began to identify that the rates of medical procedures varied significantly along geographic and socioeconomic lines. Dr. J. Alison Glover recognized that tonsillectomy rates in school children in certain school districts in England and Wales were in some cases eight times the rates of children in other (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45. Accountability and Close-Call Counterfactuals: The Loser Who Nearly Won and the Winner Who Nearly Lost.Keith Markman & Philip Tetlock - 2000 - Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 26 (10):1213-1224.
    This article links recent work on assimilative and contrastive counterfactual thinking with research on the impact of accountability on judgment and choice. Relative to participants who felt accountable solely for bottom-line performance outcomes, participants who were accountable for their decision-making process (a) had more pronounced differential reactions to clearly winning versus (winning but) nearly losing and to clearly losing versus (losing but) nearly winning; (b) were less satisfied with the quality of their decisions when they nearly lost and more satisfied (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. The myth of the neutral 'man'.Janice Moulton - 1981 - In Mary Vetterling-Braggin, Sexist language: a modern philosophical analysis. Totowa, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams. pp. 100--16.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47. "I Couldn't Have Known": Accountability, Foreseeability, and Counterfactual Denials of Responsibility.Keith Markman & Philip Tetlock - 2000 - British Journal of Social Psychology 39:313-325.
    This article explores situational determinants and psychological consequences of counterfactual excuse-making - denying responsibility by declaring `I couldn’t have known.’ Participants who were made accountable for a stock investment decision that resulted in an outcome caused by unforeseeable circumstances were particularly likely to generate counterfactual excuses and, as a result, to deny responsibility for the outcome of their choices and minimize their perceptions of control over the decision process. The article discusses the implications of these findings for structuring accountability reporting (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  88
    Duelism in Philosophy.Janice Moulton - 1980 - Teaching Philosophy 3 (4):419-433.
  49. Sexual behavior: Another position.Janice Moulton - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (16):537-546.
  50.  28
    Announcement.Benjamin W. Moulton, Kathleen M. Boozang & Edward J. Hutchinson - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (4):740-740.
1 — 50 / 959